« Supplementary Exercises*: Well-Ordering: Problem 7 Solution

Supplementary Exercises*: Well-Ordering: Problem 8 Solution

Working problems is a crucial part of learning mathematics. No one can learn topology merely by poring over the definitions, theorems, and examples that are worked out in the text. One must work part of it out for oneself. To provide that opportunity is the purpose of the exercises.
James R. Munkres
Using Exercises 1-4, construct an uncountable well-ordered set, as follows. Let be the collection of all pairs , where is a subset of and is a well-ordering of . (We allow to be empty.) Define if and have the same order type. It is trivial to show this is an equivalence relation. Let denote the equivalence class of ; let denote the collection of these equivalence classes. Define if has the order type of a section of .
(a) Show that the relation is well defined and is a simple order on . Note that the equivalence class is the smallest element of .
(b) Show that if is an element of , then has the same order type as the section of by . [Hint: Define a map by setting for each .]
(c) Conclude that is well-ordered by .
(d) Show that is uncountable. [Hint: If is a bijection, then gives rise to a well-ordering of .]
(a) "Well defined" means that the relation does not depend on the choice of representing a class. It does not, as all pairs in one class have the same order type. Then, using Exercises 2(b) and 4(a), the relation is non-reflexive and every two equivalence classes are comparable. Finally, transitivity follows from the fact that a section of a section is a section.
(b) Define the map as in the hint. This is an order preserving injection, as if then is a section of . Moreover, for every , is a subsection of , so . Now, if , then there is an order preserving bijection from onto a section , and . Therefore, is an order preserving bijection from onto .
(c) Take any element of a nonempty subset . If is not the smallest element of ( is not empty), we show that there is one. has the same order type as , and there is the order preserving bijection defined in (b). Then, is the smallest element in . (Simply said, by (b), every section of is well-ordered, hence, so is .)
(d) is infinite, as for every , and for , and have different order types (for example, Exercise 2(b)). Suppose is countable and is a bijection. Define the order on such that iff . This is a well-ordering, and it has the same type as on ( is an order preserving bijection). But from (b) we know that has the same order type as . Therefore, we conclude that has the same order type as one of its sections. Contradiction to Exercise 2(b). Hence, there is no bijection of with , and is uncountable.
Note, by the way, that for any , has the same order type as , and is countable. Therefore, by Exercise 4(b), the constructed well-ordered set is the minimal uncountable well-ordered set.
The same argument as in (d) can be applied to any other set . We start by considering all possible well-orderings on subsets of (including itself and the empty set). We define the set of the classes of well-ordered subsets having the same order type, define the well-ordering on as before, and show that each element of each class has the same order type as the section of by this class. Since includes all possible well-orderings on , neither one can have the same order type as the constructed well-ordering on , otherwise would have the same order type as one of its sections. Therefore, is a well-ordered set having greater cardinality than (if they had the same cardinality there would be a bijection giving rise to a well-ordering on having the same order type as ; the argument is the same as in (d)).
For example, let us start with the empty set . It has one well-ordered subset, and . Let us denote by the symbol . Now, on is empty, hence, we have a one-element well-ordered set . Further, let the one element set . Then, there are two well-ordered subsets of , and where as has the order type of . Let us denote by the symbol . The constructed is a well-ordered two-element set, where . Now, having a two-element set , there are five well-ordered subsets of (can you name them all?), but only three classes of equivalent well-orderings (this is where the equivalence of well-orderings starts mattering). Moreover, the type of the order depends only on the number of elements in the subset (Theorem 10.1), and for different numbers of elements we have different orders (Exercise 2(b)). Hence, as representatives for the classes of equivalent well-orderings we can choose , and . Therefore, we have Let us denote by the symbol . Then, clearly, . The constructed is a well-ordered three-element set. We can continue this way. Having an -element set , the set of all well-ordered subsets of consists of approximately ( ) well-ordered subsets, where each class of equivalent -element subsets consists of subsets. Then, the set where is the usual order. We denote by . Then, Now, let be the set of all , . Then, the classes of equivalent well-ordered subsets of include all finite well-orderings, i.e. , as well as all order types of countably infinite well-orderings. What we prove in (d) is that there are uncountably many countably infinite order types, and is uncountable.