Supplementary Exercises*: Well-Ordering: Problem 8 Solution
Working problems is a crucial part of learning mathematics. No one can learn topology merely by poring over the definitions, theorems, and examples that are worked out in the text. One must work part of it out for oneself. To provide that opportunity is the purpose of the exercises.
James R. Munkres
Using Exercises 1-4, construct an uncountable well-ordered set, as follows. Let
be the collection of all pairs
, where
is a subset of
and
is a well-ordering of
. (We allow
to be empty.) Define
if
and
have the same order type. It is trivial to show this is an equivalence relation. Let
denote the equivalence class of
; let
denote the collection of these equivalence classes. Define
if
has the order type of a section of
.
(a) Show that the relation
is well defined and is a simple order on
. Note that the equivalence class
is the smallest element of
.
(b) Show that if
is an element of
, then
has the same order type as the section
of
by
. [Hint: Define a map
by setting
for each
.]
(c) Conclude that
is well-ordered by
.
(d) Show that
is uncountable. [Hint: If
is a bijection, then
gives rise to a well-ordering of
.]
(a) "Well defined" means that the relation does not depend on the choice of
representing a class. It does not, as all pairs in one class have the same order type. Then, using Exercises 2(b) and 4(a), the relation is non-reflexive and every two equivalence classes are comparable. Finally, transitivity follows from the fact that a section of a section is a section.
(b) Define the map
as in the hint. This is an order preserving injection, as if
then
is a section of
. Moreover, for every
,
is a subsection of
, so
. Now, if
, then there is an order preserving bijection from
onto a section
, and
. Therefore,
is an order preserving bijection from
onto
.
(c) Take any element
of a nonempty subset
. If
is not the smallest element of
(
is not empty), we show that there is one.
has the same order type as
, and there is the order preserving bijection
defined in (b). Then,
is the smallest element in
. (Simply said, by (b), every section of
is well-ordered, hence, so is
.)
(d)
is infinite, as
for every
, and for
,
and
have different order types (for example, Exercise 2(b)). Suppose
is countable and
is a bijection. Define the order
on
such that
iff
. This is a well-ordering, and it has the same type as
on
(
is an order preserving bijection). But from (b) we know that
has the same order type as
. Therefore, we conclude that
has the same order type as one of its sections. Contradiction to Exercise 2(b). Hence, there is no bijection of
with
, and
is uncountable.
Note, by the way, that for any
,
has the same order type as
, and
is countable. Therefore, by Exercise 4(b), the constructed well-ordered set is the minimal uncountable well-ordered set.
The same argument as in (d) can be applied to any other set
. We start by considering all possible well-orderings on subsets of
(including
itself and the empty set). We define the set
of the classes of well-ordered subsets having the same order type, define the well-ordering
on
as before, and show that each element of each class has the same order type as the section of
by this class. Since
includes all possible well-orderings on
, neither one can have the same order type as the constructed well-ordering on
, otherwise
would have the same order type as one of its sections. Therefore,
is a well-ordered set having greater cardinality than
(if they had the same cardinality there would be a bijection giving rise to a well-ordering on
having the same order type as
; the argument is the same as in (d)).
For example, let us start with the empty set
. It has one well-ordered subset, and
. Let us denote
by the symbol
. Now,
on
is empty, hence, we have a one-element well-ordered set
. Further, let the one element set
. Then, there are two well-ordered subsets of
, and
where
as
has the order type of
. Let us denote
by the symbol
. The constructed
is a well-ordered two-element set, where
. Now, having a two-element set
, there are five well-ordered subsets of
(can you name them all?), but only three classes of equivalent well-orderings (this is where the equivalence of well-orderings starts mattering). Moreover, the type of the order depends only on the number of elements in the subset (Theorem 10.1), and for different numbers of elements we have different orders (Exercise 2(b)). Hence, as representatives for the classes of equivalent well-orderings we can choose
,
and
. Therefore, we have
Let us denote
by the symbol
. Then, clearly,
. The constructed
is a well-ordered three-element set. We can continue this way. Having an
-element set
, the set of all well-ordered subsets of
consists of approximately
(
) well-ordered subsets, where each class of equivalent
-element subsets consists of
subsets. Then, the set
where
is the usual order. We denote
by
. Then,
Now, let
be the set of all
,
. Then, the classes of equivalent well-ordered subsets of
include all finite well-orderings, i.e.
, as well as all order types of countably infinite well-orderings. What we prove in (d) is that there are uncountably many countably infinite order types, and
is uncountable.